Jaina seven-valued logic

Summary

Jaina seven-valued logic is a system of argumentation developed by Jaina philosophers and thinkers in ancient India to support and substantiate their theory of pluralism. This argumentation system has seven distinct semantic predicates which may be thought of as seven different truth values. Traditionally, in the Jaina and other Indian literature dealing with topics in Jain philosophy, this system of argumentation is referred to as Saptabhangivada or Syadvada. The earliest reference to Syadvada occurs is the writings of Bhadrabahu (c. 433–357 BCE). There is mention of Syadvada in the Nyayavatara of Siddhasena Divakara (about 480–550 CE). Samantabhadra (about 600 CE) gave a full exposition of the seven parts of Syadvada or Saptabhanginyaya in his Aptamimamsa. The Syadvadamanjari of Mallisena (1292 CE) is a separate treatise on the same theory. There are, of course, still later works and a large number of modern commentaries.[1] The interpretation of Saptabhangivada as a seven-valued logic was attempted by Harvard University philosophy professor George Bosworth Burch (1902–1973) in a paper published in International Philosophical Quarterly in the year 1964.[2] P. C. Mahalanobis, an Indian applied statistician, has given a probabilistic interpretation of the Saptabhangivada.[1][3]

The seven predicates edit

The Saptabhangivada, the seven predicate theory may be summarized as follows:[4]

The seven predicate theory consists in the use of seven claims about sentences, each preceded by "arguably" or "conditionally" (syat), concerning a single object and its particular properties, composed of assertions and denials, either simultaneously or successively, and without contradiction. These seven claims are the following.

  1. Arguably, it (that is, some object) exists (syad asty eva).
  2. Arguably, it does not exist (syan nasty eva).
  3. Arguably, it exists; arguably, it doesn't exist (syad asty eva syan nasty eva).
  4. Arguably, it is non-assertible (syad avaktavyam eva).
  5. Arguably, it exists; arguably, it is non-assertible (syad asty eva syad avaktavyam eva).
  6. Arguably, it doesn't exist; arguably, it is non-assertible (syan nasty eva syad avaktavyam eva).
  7. Arguably, it exists; arguably, it doesn't exist; arguably it is non-assertible (syad asty eva syan nasty eva syad avaktavyam eva).

There are three basic truth values, namely, true (t), false (f) and unassertible (u). These are combined to produce four more truth values, namely, tf, tu, fu, and tfu (Three-valued logic). Though, superficially, it appears that there are only three distinct truth values a deeper analysis of the Jaina system reveals that the seven truth values are indeed distinct. This is a consequence of the conditionalising operator "arguably" denoted in Sanskrit by the word syat. This Sanskrit word has the literal meaning of "perhaps it is", and it is used to mean "from a certain standpoint" or "within a particular philosophical perspective".

In this discussion the term "standpoint" has been used in a technical sense. Consider a situation in which a globally inconsistent set of propositions, the totality of philosophical discourse, is divided into sub-sets, each of which is internally consistent. Any proposition might be supported by others from within the same sub-set. At the same time, the negation of that proposition might occur in a distinct, though possibly overlapping subset, and be supported by other propositions within it. Each such consistent sub-set of a globally inconsistent discourse, is what the Jainas call a "standpoint" (naya). A standpoint corresponds to a particular philosophical perspective.[4]

In this terminology, it can be seen that the seven predicates get translated to the following seven possibilities. Each proposition p has the following seven states:[4]

  1. p is a member of every standpoint in S.
  2. Not-p is a member of every standpoint in S.
  3. p is a member of some standpoints, and Not-p is a member of the rest.
  4. p is a member of some standpoints, the rest being neutral.
  5. Not-p is a member of some standpoints, the rest being neutral.
  6. p is neutral with respect to every standpoint.
  7. p is a member of some standpoints and Not-p is a member of some other standpoints, and the rest are neutral.

Comparison with Catuskoti and Aristotelian Logic edit

Saptabhangi Logic Catuṣkoṭi Logic Aristotelian logic
It is : (P) It is : (P) It is : (P)
It is not : (P') It is not : (P') It is not : (P')
It is and it is not : (P^P') It is and it is not : (P^P')
It is unassertible : (U(P)) It is neither : (P^P')'
It is and it is unassertible : (P^U(P))
It is not and it is unassertible : (P'^U(P))
It is and it is not and it is unassertible  : (P^P'^U(P))
Negation Table
Logical Truth value

P

Negation

~P

True False
Unassertible Unassertible
False True

Further reading edit

  • For the implementation of a generic computational argumentation system to Jaina seven-valued logic, see Ohta, Shogo; Hagiwara, Takeshi; Sawamura, Hajime; Riche, Jacques (2013). "Specializing the Logic of Multiple-Valued Argumentation to the Jaina Seven-Valued Logic" (PDF). Proceedings on the International Conference on Artificial Intelligence: 1–7. Retrieved 5 June 2022.
  • For an exposition of the Jaina concept of logic, see V. K. Bharadwaja (July 1982). "The Jaina Concept of Logic" (PDF). Indian Philosophical Quarterly. IX (4): 362–376. Retrieved 27 November 2016.
  • For an exposition stating that Saptabhangi cannot be considered as logic in the modern sense of the word, see Fabien Schang (December 2013). "A One-Valued Logic for Non-One-Sidedness". International Journal of Jaina Studies. 9 (4): 1–25. Retrieved 28 November 2016.
  • For an exposition of Saptabhangi, see Pragati Jain (July 2000). "Saptabhaṅgī: The Jaina Theory of Sevenfold Predication: A Logical Analysis" (PDF). Philosophy East and West. 50 (3): 385–399. Retrieved 28 November 2016.
  • For a discussion on Syadvada, see J. B. S. Haldane. "The Syadvada System of Predication". Jain World. Archived from the original on 16 June 2008. Retrieved 28 November 2016. (Sankhya 18, 195–200, 1957)
  • Marie-Hélène Gorisse, Nicolas Clerbout and Shahid Rahman [fr] developed a dialogical approach to the theory of standpoints.[5]

References edit

  1. ^ a b P.C. Mahalanobis. "The Indian-Jaina Dialectic of Syadvad in Relation to Probability (I)". Jain World. Archived from the original on 23 November 2005. Retrieved 28 November 2016. (Dialectica 8, 1954, 95–111)
  2. ^ George Bosworth Burch (February 1964). "Seven-Valued Logic in Jain Philosophy". International Philosophical Quarterly. 4 (1): 68–93. doi:10.5840/ipq19644140.
  3. ^ P.C. Mahalanobis. "The Indian-Jaina Dialectic of Syadvad in Relation to Probability (II)". Jain World. Retrieved 28 November 2016. (Dialectica 8, 1954, 95–111)
  4. ^ a b c Jonardon Ganeri (2002). "Jaina Logic and the Philosophical Basis of Pluralism". History and Philosophy of Logic. 23 (4): 267–281. doi:10.1080/0144534021000051505. S2CID 170089234. Retrieved 28 November 2016.
  5. ^ “Context Sensitivity in Jain Philosophy. A Dialogical Study of Siddharsigani’s Commentary on the Handbook of Logic”. S. Rahman/ N. Clerbout/ M. H. Gorisse. Journal of Philosophical Logic, volume 40, number 5 (2011), pp. 633-662