Predication (philosophy)

Summary

Predication in philosophy refers to an act of judgement where one term is subsumed under another.[1] A comprehensive conceptualization describes it as the understanding of the relation expressed by a predicative structure primordially (i.e. both originally and primarily) through the opposition between particular and general or the one and the many.[1]

Plato and Aristotle used predication to address the Problem of Universals.

Predication is also associated or used interchangeably with the concept of attribution where both terms pertain to the way judgment and ideas acquire a new property in the second operation of the mind (or the mental operation of judging[2]).[3]

Background edit

Predication emerged when ancient philosophers began exploring reality and the two entities that divide it: properties and the things that bear them.[4] These thinkers investigated what the division between thing and property amounted to. It was argued that the relationship resembled the logical analysis of a sentence wherein the division of subject and predicate arises spontaneously.[4] It was Aristotle who posited that the division between subject and predicate is fundamental and that there is no truth unless a property is "predicated of" something.[4] In Plato's works, predication is demonstrated in the analysis of desire.[5] He stated through Socrates that the type of dominant excess gives its name to the one who has it such as how drunkenness gives its name to a drunkard.[5] Here, predication confirms the reality of this form of excess on the being who partakes in it.[5] Pythagoreans also touched on predication as they explained how number is the essence of everything.[6] They hold that a number has an independent reality, arguing that substances such as fire and water were not the real essences of the things they are predicated.[6] In describing Greek philosophy, Charles Kahn identified predication as one of the three concepts - along with truth and reality - that ontology connected.[7]

It is suggested that predication is equivalent to the German concept of Aussage.[8] In Grundlagen, for instance, Gottlob Frege used this term to state that a statement of a number contains a predication about a concept.[8] As a counterpart of Aussage, predication also appeared in J.C.A. Heyse's Deutsche Grammatik (1814), which influenced the development of the Japanese notion of predication called chinjutsu.[9] This concept was developed by the Japanese logician Yamada Yoshio, who used it to establish the study of modality.[9] Chinjutsu would later be explored by other Japanese logicians such as Takeo Miyake, Minoru Watanabe, and Motoki Tokieda.[10]

Theories edit

In the philosophy of language, predication is distinguished from the linguistic predication with the notion that a predicable is a metaphysical item and is ontologically predicated of its predicand, usually its subject.[11] The subjects are also distinguished: in linguistic predication, a subject is a grammatical item while in philosophy, it is an item in the ontology.[12] The Aristotelian conceptualization of predication, for instance, focused on the metaphysical configurations that underlie sentences.[12] There are scholars who note that Aristotle's thought on the subject can be distinguished in two levels: ontological (where predicates pertain to things); and, logical (where predicates are something that is said of things).[12] Like Plato, Aristotle used predication to address the Problem of Universals.[13]

In Fregean semantics, predication is described as the relation where "an argument saturates an open position in the function, cf. the simplified formula".[12] In Abū’l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī’s scientific philosophy, predication is the judgment of the existence of a thing towards a thing.[14] It does not constitute a judgment of the world while judgment is the assumption of the predication. It is also considered a completed notion.[14]

According to Willard Van Orman Quine, predication involves the act of connecting singular terms in a referential position and general terms in a predicative position where, in the composed sentence, both terms have different roles.[15] He maintained that predicates do not name, stand for, or rely on the existence of abstract entities (e.g. properties, relations, sets).[16] The way he linked predicates to the things of which they can be predicated is not seen as a full account of the role of the predicates but this allowed his notion to avoid a regress.[16]

Gilles Deleuze maintained that predication is not attribution since substance is not a subject of attribute.[17] In his description of the schema of attribution, Deleuze maintained that the predicate is above all relation and event, not attribute.[18] He drew from Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz' conceptualization of the event, which holds that "the predicate is a verb, and that the verb is irreducible to the copula and to the attribute."[17] The thinker posited that "the world itself is an event and, as an incorporeal (=virtual) predicate, the world must be included in every subject."[19] He maintained that everything has a reason, examining causality by identifying an event as that which happens to a thing with or without cause or reason.[20]

The German philosopher Gottlob Frege also developed his own theory of predication, which held that we can discern first-level predications in a simple proposition in the same way we can identify linguistic functions of a certain kind - one that yield the proposition as value once applied as arguments to one or more constituent names.[21] His conceptual notation, which is taken to mean as universal language, stressed the distinctions between objects and properties or concepts. He maintained that different configurations are necessary for us to speak about objects due to its role in the consideration of the relationship between our language and the objects themselves.[22]

The modern conceptualization of predication describes predication as the foundation or the condition of possibility of sense where sense is approached as belonging to thought and to the ways thought relates to things.[1]

Classifications edit

Aristotle said that predication can be kath hauto when the predicated universal identifies the subject as what it is, marking this type as de re necessary.[23][24] It is distinguished from kata sumbebekos predication, which is concerned with how-predication or when the predicated universal merely modifies or characterizes a subject that is antecedently identified as what it is by another universal.[24]

St. Thomas Aquinas explained that attribution or predication may be essential/substantial (per se) or accidental (per accidens).[25] It is per se if the predicate refers to something that belongs to the subject by definition while it is per accidens when a property is attributed to something that is not its own subject.[3] Aquinas also proposed other types of predication such as negative and affirmative, categorical and hypothetical, in necessary and contingent matter, and universal and particular, among others.[3]

E. J. Lowe also proposed two types of predication: dispositional and occurrent.[26] The former describes an object's belonging to a kind possessing some property while the latter describes an object's possessing a trope of some property.[27] A third type was also proposed but it is a dispositional variant to express a law of nature.[27]

Applications edit

 
The Predication of Saint Paul

In addressing the Problem of Universals, Aristotle established a kind of predication where universal terms are involved in a relation of predication provided some facts that are expressed by ordinary sentences hold.[28] It is also argued that the particular instantiates or participates in the universal, hence, universals may be needed for the predication of relations.[29]

Predication is also used to explain the indeterminacy of mass terms.[30] When mass terms are treated as predicates, indeterminacy is demonstrated when the terms are applied to combination of quantities by being portions of such combinations as well as to quantities that are qualified in other ways.[30]

In the Pauline theology, the apostle Paul employed predication to explain the qualities of God.[31] He maintained, for instance, that "form" is a predication of God and it also serves as a predication of "Christ Jesus".[32] Paul argued that God has a form and Jesus exists in this form.[32]

References edit

  1. ^ a b c Freudenthal, G. (2013). Salomon Maimon: Rational Dogmatist, Empirical Skeptic: Critical Assessments. Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media. p. 59. ISBN 9789048163632.
  2. ^ Thomas, John of St (1962). Outlines of Formal Logic, Second Printing. Translated by Wade, Francis. Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Marquette University Press. p. 6.
  3. ^ a b c Mondin, Battista (2012). St. Thomas Aquinas' Philosophy: In the Commentary to the Sentences. Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 9789024717330.
  4. ^ a b c Scruton, Roger (2012). Modern Philosophy: An Introduction and Survey. A&C Black. ISBN 978-1-4482-1051-0.
  5. ^ a b c White, David A. (1993). Rhetoric and Reality in Plato's "Phaedrus". New York: SUNY Press. p. 41. ISBN 978-1-4384-2398-2.
  6. ^ a b Burnet, John (1892). Early Greek Philosophy. London: Adam and Charles Black. pp. 308–309.
  7. ^ Reding, Jean-Paul (2017-03-02). Comparative Essays in Early Greek and Chinese Rational Thinking. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-95005-3.
  8. ^ a b Frege, Gottlob; Cook, Roy T. (2013). Gottlob Frege: Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. xvii. ISBN 978-0-19-928174-9.
  9. ^ a b Narrog, Heiko (2009). Modality in Japanese: The Layered Structure of the Clause and Hierarchies of Functional Categories. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing. p. 22. ISBN 978-90-272-0576-6.
  10. ^ Pizziconi, Barbara; Kizu, Mika (2009). Japanese Modality: Exploring its Scope and Interpretation. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 16–17. ISBN 978-0-230-24575-4.
  11. ^ Lewis, Frank A.; Lewis, Professor of Philosophy Frank A. (1991). Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge, UK: CUP Archive. p. 55. ISBN 0-521-39159-8.
  12. ^ a b c d Stalmaszczyk, Piotr (2014). Philosophy of Language and Linguistics: The Legacy of Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein. Berlin/Boston: Walter de Gruyter GmbH & Co KG. pp. 238–239. ISBN 978-3-11-034258-1.
  13. ^ Loux, Michael J. (2001). Metaphysics: Contemporary Readings. London: Routledge. p. 3. ISBN 0-415-26108-2.
  14. ^ a b Pavlov, Moshe M. (2016). Abū'l-Barakāt al-Baghdādī's Scientific Philosophy: The Kitāb al-Mu'tabar. Oxon: Taylor & Francis. p. 210. ISBN 9781138640450.
  15. ^ Preyer, Gerhard (2006). Donald Davidson's Philosophy: From Radical Interpretation to Radical Contextualism. Frankfurt: Humanities Online. p. 300. ISBN 978-3-941743-11-3.
  16. ^ a b Davidson, Donald (2005). Truth and Predication. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. pp. 114. ISBN 0-674-01525-8.
  17. ^ a b Holland, Eugene W.; Smith, Daniel W.; Stivale, Charles J. (2009). Gilles Deleuze: Image and Text. London: Continuum. pp. 235. ISBN 978-0826408327.
  18. ^ Boundas, Constantin V.; Olkowski, Dorothea (2017). Gilles Deleuze and the Theater of Philosophy. Oxon: Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-62222-6.
  19. ^ Bell, Jeffrey A. (2016). Deleuze and Guattari's What is Philosophy?. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. ISBN 978-0-7486-9255-2.
  20. ^ Stivale, Charles J. (2011). Gilles Deleuze: Key Concepts, Second Edition. Oxon: Routledge. p. 200. ISBN 978-1-84465-287-7.
  21. ^ Beaney, Michael; Reck, Erich H. (2005). Gottlob Frege: Frege's philosophy of thought and language, Volume IV. Oxon: Taylor & Francis. p. 129. ISBN 0-415-30605-1.
  22. ^ Haaparanta, L.; Hintikka, Jaakko (2012). Frege Synthesized: Essays on the Philosophical and Foundational Work of Gottlob Frege. Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media. p. 167. ISBN 978-94-010-8523-6.
  23. ^ Dahl, Norman O. (2019). Substance in Aristotle's Metaphysics Zeta. Cham, Switzerland: Palgrave Macmillan. p. 8. ISBN 978-3-030-22160-7.
  24. ^ a b Galluzzo, Gabriele; Loux, Michael J. (2015). The Problem of Universals in Contemporary Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 34. ISBN 978-1-107-10089-3.
  25. ^ Aertsen, Jan (1988). Nature and Creature: Thomas Aquinas's Way of Thought. Leiden: BRILL. p. 54. ISBN 90-04-08451-7.
  26. ^ Gnassounou, Bruno; Kistler, Max (2016). Dispositions and Causal Powers. Oxon: Routledge. p. 117. ISBN 9780754654254.
  27. ^ a b Bennett, Brandon; Fellbaum, Christiane (2006). Formal Ontology in Information Systems: Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference (FOIS 2006). Amsterdam: IOS Press. pp. 139. ISBN 1-58603-685-8.
  28. ^ Pinzani, Roberto (2018). The Problem of Universals from Boethius to John of Salisbury. Leiden: BRILL. p. 2. ISBN 978-90-04-37115-6.
  29. ^ Kuipers, Theo (2007). General Philosophy of Science: Focal Issues. Amsterdam: Elsevier. pp. 310. ISBN 9780444515483.
  30. ^ a b Pelletier, Francis Jeffrey (2007). Mass Terms: Some Philosophical Problems. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. p. 47. ISBN 978-1-4020-3265-3.
  31. ^ Breton, Stanislas (2011). A Radical Philosophy of Saint Paul. New York: Columbia University Press. p. 977. ISBN 978-0-231-15104-7.
  32. ^ a b Lenski, R. C. H. (2008). The Interpretation of St. Paul's Epistles to the Ephesians and Philippians. Minneapolis: Augsburg Fortress. p. 775. ISBN 9780806680828.