Proof of Bertrand's postulate

Summary

In mathematics, Bertrand's postulate (actually now a theorem) states that for each there is a prime such that . First conjectured in 1845 by Joseph Bertrand,[1] it was first proven by Chebyshev, and a shorter but also advanced proof was given by Ramanujan.[2]

The following elementary proof was published by Paul Erdős in 1932, as one of his earliest mathematical publications.[3] The basic idea is to show that the central binomial coefficients need to have a prime factor within the interval in order to be large enough. This is achieved through analysis of the factorization of the central binomial coefficients.

The main steps of the proof are as follows. First, show that the contribution of every prime power factor in the prime decomposition of the central binomial coefficient is at most . Then show that every prime larger than appears at most once.

The next step is to prove that has no prime factors in the interval . As a consequence of these bounds, the contribution to the size of coming from the prime factors that are at most grows asymptotically as for some . Since the asymptotic growth of the central binomial coefficient is at least , the conclusion is that, by contradiction and for large enough , the binomial coefficient must have another prime factor, which can only lie between and .

The argument given is valid for all . The remaining values of  are by direct inspection, which completes the proof.

Lemmas in the proof edit

The proof uses the following four lemmas to establish facts about the primes present in the central binomial coefficients.

Lemma 1 edit

For any integer  , we have

 

Proof: Applying the binomial theorem,

 

since   is the largest term in the sum in the right-hand side, and the sum has   terms (including the initial   outside the summation).

Lemma 2 edit

For a fixed prime  , define   to be the p-adic order of  , that is, the largest natural number   such that   divides  .

For any prime  ,  .

Proof: The exponent of   in   is given by Legendre's formula

 

so

 

But each term of the last summation must be either zero (if  ) or one (if  ), and all terms with   are zero. Therefore,

 

and

 

Lemma 3 edit

If   is odd and prime and  , then  

Proof: There are exactly two factors of   in the numerator of the expression  , coming from the two terms   and   in  , and also two factors of   in the denominator from one copy of the term   in each of the two factors of  . These factors all cancel, leaving no factors of   in  . (The bound on   in the preconditions of the lemma ensures that   is too large to be a term of the numerator, and the assumption that   is odd is needed to ensure that   contributes only one factor of   to the numerator.)

Lemma 4 edit

An upper bound is supplied for the primorial function,

 

where the product is taken over all prime numbers   less than or equal to  .

For all  ,  .

Proof: We use complete induction.

For   we have   and  .

Let us assume that the inequality hold for all  . Since   is composite, we have

 

Now let us assume that the inequality hold for all  . Since   is an integer and all the primes   appear only in the numerator, we have

 

therefore,

 

Proof of Bertrand's Postulate edit

Assume that there is a counterexample: an integer n ≥ 2 such that there is no prime p  with n < p < 2n.

If 2 ≤ n < 427, then p can be chosen from among the prime numbers 3, 5, 7, 13, 23, 43, 83, 163, 317, 631 (each being the largest prime less than twice its predecessor) such that n < p < 2n. Therefore, n ≥ 427.

There are no prime factors p of   such that:

  • 2n < p, because every factor must divide (2n)!;
  • p = 2n, because 2n is not prime;
  • n < p < 2n, because we assumed there is no such prime number;
  • 2n / 3 < pn: by Lemma 3.

Therefore, every prime factor p satisfies p ≤ 2n / 3.

When   the number   has at most one factor of p. By Lemma 2, for any prime p we have pR(p,n) ≤ 2n, and   since 1 is neither prime nor composite. Then, starting with Lemma 1 and decomposing the right-hand side into its prime factorization, and finally using Lemma 4, these bounds give:

 

we get the equivalent inequalities

 

Taking logarithms yields to

 

By concavity of the right-hand side as a function of n, the last inequality is necessarily verified on an interval. Since it holds true for   and it does not for  , we obtain

 

But these cases have already been settled, and we conclude that no counterexample to the postulate is possible.

Addendum to proof edit

It is possible to reduce the bound to  .

For   we get  , so we can say that the product   is at most  , which gives

 

which is true for   and false for  .

References edit

  1. ^ Bertrand, Joseph (1845), "Mémoire sur le nombre de valeurs que peut prendre une fonction quand on y permute les lettres qu'elle renferme.", Journal de l'École Royale Polytechnique (in French), 18 (Cahier 30): 123–140.
  2. ^ Ramanujan, S. (1919), "A proof of Bertrand's postulate", Journal of the Indian Mathematical Society, 11: 181–182
  3. ^ {{citation  | last = Erdős | first = Pál | author-link = Paul Erdős  | journal = Acta Litt. Sci. Szeged  | language = de  | pages = 194–198  | title = Beweis eines Satzes von Tschebyschef  | trans-title = Proof of a theorem of Chebyshev  | url = https://users.renyi.hu/~p_erdos/1932-01.pdf  | volume = 5  | year = 1932  | zbl = 0004.10103}}

External links edit

  • Chebyshev's Theorem and Bertrand's Postulate (Leo Goldmakher): https://web.williams.edu/Mathematics/lg5/Chebyshev.pdf
  • Proof of Bertrand's Postulate (UW Math Circle): https://sites.math.washington.edu/~mathcircle/circle/2013-14/advanced/mc-13a-w10.pdf
  • Proof in the Mizar system: http://mizar.org/version/current/html/nat_4.html#T56
  • Weisstein, Eric W. "Bertrand's Postulate". MathWorld.