Rational consequence relation

Summary

In logic, a rational consequence relation is a non-monotonic consequence relation satisfying certain properties listed below.

A rational consequence relation is a logical framework that refines traditional deductive reasoning to better model real-world scenarios. It incorporates rules like reflexivity, left logical equivalence, right-hand weakening, cautious monotony, disjunction on the left-hand side, logical and on the right-hand side, and rational monotony. These rules enable the relation to handle everyday situations more effectively by allowing for non-monotonic reasoning, where conclusions can be drawn based on usual rather than absolute implications. This approach is particularly useful in cases where adding more information can change the outcome, providing a more nuanced understanding than monotone consequence relations.

Properties edit

A rational consequence relation   satisfies:

REF
Reflexivity  

and the so-called GabbayMakinson rules:[citation needed]

LLE
Left logical equivalence  
RWE
Right-hand weakening  
CMO
Cautious monotonicity  
DIS
Logical or (i.e. disjunction) on left hand side  
AND
Logical and on right hand side  
RMO
Rational monotonicity  [clarification needed]

Uses edit

The rational consequence relation is non-monotonic, and the relation   is intended to carry the meaning theta usually implies phi or phi usually follows from theta. In this sense it is more useful for modeling some everyday situations than a monotone consequence relation because the latter relation models facts in a more strict boolean fashion—something either follows under all circumstances or it does not.

Example: cake edit

The statement "If a cake contains sugar then it tastes good" implies under a monotone consequence relation the statement "If a cake contains sugar and soap then it tastes good." Clearly this doesn't match our own understanding of cakes. By asserting "If a cake contains sugar then it usually tastes good" a rational consequence relation allows for a more realistic model of the real world, and certainly it does not automatically follow that "If a cake contains sugar and soap then it usually tastes good."

Note that if we also have the information "If a cake contains sugar then it usually contains butter" then we may legally conclude (under CMO) that "If a cake contains sugar and butter then it usually tastes good.". Equally in the absence of a statement such as "If a cake contains sugar then usually it contains no soap" then we may legally conclude from RMO that "If the cake contains sugar and soap then it usually tastes good."

If this latter conclusion seems ridiculous to you then it is likely that you are subconsciously asserting your own preconceived knowledge about cakes when evaluating the validity of the statement. That is, from your experience you know that cakes that contain soap are likely to taste bad so you add to the system your own knowledge such as "Cakes that contain sugar do not usually contain soap.", even though this knowledge is absent from it. If the conclusion seems silly to you then you might consider replacing the word soap with the word eggs to see if it changes your feelings.

Example: drugs edit

Consider the sentences:

  • Young people are usually happy
  • Drug abusers are usually not happy
  • Drug abusers are usually young

We may consider it reasonable to conclude:

  • Young drug abusers are usually not happy

This would not be a valid conclusion under a monotonic deduction system (omitting of course the word 'usually'), since the third sentence would contradict the first two. In contrast the conclusion follows immediately using the Gabbay–Makinson rules: applying the rule CMO to the last two sentences yields the result.

Consequences edit

The following consequences follow from the above rules:

MP
Modus ponens  
MP is proved via the rules AND and RWE.
CON
Conditionalisation  
CC
Cautious cut  
The notion of cautious cut simply encapsulates the operation of conditionalisation, followed by MP. It may seem redundant in this sense, but it is often used in proofs so it is useful to have a name for it to act as a shortcut.
SCL
Supraclassity  
SCL is proved trivially via REF and RWE.

Rational consequence relations via atom preferences edit

Let   be a finite language. An atom is a formula of the form   (where   and  ). Notice that there is a unique valuation which makes any given atom true (and conversely each valuation satisfies precisely one atom). Thus an atom can be used to represent a preference about what we believe ought to be true.

Let   be the set of all atoms in L. For   SL, define  .

Let   be a sequence of subsets of  . For  ,   in SL, let the relation   be such that   if one of the following holds:

  1.   for each  
  2.   for some   and for the least such i,  .

Then the relation   is a rational consequence relation. This may easily be verified by checking directly that it satisfies the GM-conditions.

The idea behind the sequence of atom sets is that the earlier sets account for the most likely situations such as "young people are usually law abiding" whereas the later sets account for the less likely situations such as "young joyriders are usually not law abiding".

Notes edit

  1. By the definition of the relation  , the relation is unchanged if we replace   with  ,   with   ... and   with  . In this way we make each   disjoint. Conversely it makes no difference to the rational consequence relation   if we add to subsequent   atoms from any of the preceding  .

The representation theorem edit

It can be proven that any rational consequence relation on a finite language is representable via a sequence of atom preferences above. That is, for any such rational consequence relation   there is a sequence   of subsets of   such that the associated rational consequence relation   is the same relation:  

Notes edit

  1. By the above property of  , the representation of a rational consequence relation   need not be unique—if the   are not disjoint then they can be made so without changing the rational consequence relation and conversely if they are disjoint then each subsequent set can contain any of the atoms of the previous sets without changing the rational consequence relation.

References edit

  • Hill, Lee C.E. (2002). "A new relationship between Maximum Entropy and the Rational Closure of a Conditional Knowledge Base". University of Manchester. [dead link]
  • D. Makinson (Mar 1994). "General Patterns in Nonmonotonic Reasoning". In D.M. Gabbay and C.J. Hogger and J.A. Robinson (ed.). Deduction Methodologies. Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming. Vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 35–110. ISBN 978-0-19-853746-5.